| |
The Ashcroft Hearings
Attorney General-designate John D.
Ashcroft has promised to "enforce whatever laws Congress chooses to enact."
However, that's not the answer the liberal-dominated Senate Judiciary
Committee wants to hear. In fact, that answer scares them.
The Committee is looking for an Attorney
General who will
selectively
enforce the laws, supporting only those laws they believe 'appropriate' and
ignoring laws inconsistent with their liberal modernist ideology. Had Al
Gore won the election, his choice for Attorney General would have furthered
their liberal crusade in removing the more "traditional" laws (e.g, sodomy) from
the books.
As in the confirmation hearings of Robert
Bork and Clarence Thomas, the issue is really about the designate's conception
or philosophy of law. The following comments
below by Phillip E. Johnson from his outstanding book,
REASON IN THE BALANCE, The Case Against NATURALISM in Science, Law &
Education provide insight into the dynamic.
LAW AND THE MORAL ORDER
The traditional [conservative] and modernist [progressive / liberal]
conceptions of law differ not just in their positions on specific
matters like abortion but in their basic understanding of what
morality is and how it influences law. For the traditionalist,
morality provides the essential background to human lawmaking. In
Sir William Blackstone's classic definition, human law is "a rule of
civil conduct, prescribed by the supreme power in a state, commanding
what is right and prohibiting what is wrong." This definition
requires much elaboration before it can explain law adequately, but it
captures a profound point. For the traditionalist there is a moral
order independent (transcendent) of what human rulers may from time to
time prefer, and law is just to the extent that it comports with that
moral order.
|
|
While God's dealing with
Israel were distinctly theocratic in nature, the Apostle Paul in the New
Testament asserts that ALL government is ordained of God and thus
assumes
the right of those with a theistic worldview to inform the higher
power.
|
This does not mean that morality leads directly to law, because
considerations of practicality, compassion and even privacy may
intervene. For example, the pre-Roe traditionalist practice
was to punish abortion as a crime much less serious than murder and to
direct enforcement efforts primarily at abortionists rather than at
their clients. Criminal law was thus in a general way consistent
with morality, but not necessarily coextensive with it. In such a
system it would be nonsense to speak of a general right to freedom from
moral coercion. That would be like saying that the fundamental law
is that there must be no laws. |
|
Sadly, the anarchist element in society gained a larger voice during the
20th century. Today, the common man has a more difficult time
seeing through such libertarian nonsense. |
From the modernist [progressive / liberal] standpoint, morality is
subjective. Some people may have the opinion that certain conduct
is immoral, but others have an equal right to disagree. The term
morality in modernist usage is usually associated with sexual
morality, and therefore with traditional prohibitions of sodomy,
fornication, adultery, and abortion. With respect to such matters
involving personal taste and one's own body, consenting adults must be
free to do as they like. [goes the liberal argument]. |
|
|
Modernist lawmaking is based not on morality but on "utility" and
"rights". The state has authority to regulate personal conduct to
the extent necessary to serve the general welfare (utility) or to
protect rights (such as a right to be free from discrimination).
Otherwise, the most basic modernist right is the right to do as one
likes--as long as one is not thereby damaging the general welfare or
infringing on the rights of others. In the modernist context, a
general right to be free from moral coercion makes perfect sense.
It merely means that an individual does not forfeit her freedom merely
because other people happen to disapprove of what she wants to do. |
|
Professor Johnson's description of "the most basic modernist right" is
the central creed for political libertarianism. See his thoughts
below on America status quo of "libertarian socialism." |
Probably the most influential American statement of the modernist
understanding of law is a famous lecture titled "The Path of the Law" by
the revered American jurist Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., delivered at the
Boston University Law School in 1897. This lecture has been so
influential in shaping the thinking of American lawyers that it might be
described as almost part of the Constitution. Holmes urged his
audience of future lawyers to put aside all notions of morality and
approach law as a science, basically the science of state coercion.
The reason people ask lawyers for advice, said Holmes, is not because
they want to hear about morality but because they want to escape the
unpleasant consequences that the law will inflict on them if they
violate some rule. Therefore, "if you want to know the law and
nothing else, you must look at it as a bad man, who cares only for the
material consequences which such knowledge [of the law] enables him to
predict, not as a good one, who finds his reasons for conduct, whether
inside or outside of it, in the vaguer sanctions of conscience." |
|
"For rulers are not a terror to good works, but to evil...for he is
God's minister, an avenger to execute wrath on him who practices evil"
Romans 13: 3,4. |
Mao Zedong's famous dictum that all power
grows out of the barrel of a gun was prefigured in Holmes's view that
law is ultimately the force that a government will bring to bear to
enforce its commands. Citizens obey the law not because they feel
morally obligated to do so but because they fear the consequences if
they do not. Just as a chemist tells me that gasoline will explode
if I bring it too near a fire, my lawyer tells me that I must pay
damages if I breach a contract, or go to jail if I steal money. Of
course if I am a "good" person I may refrain from promise-breaking and
theft for independent reasons, but this, according to Holmes, has
nothing to do with law. Goodness has no important role in legal
science, because bad as well as good persons can be compelled to obey
the law. |
|
Because of its adherence to relativism, the absence of "moral
obligation" is the mark of modern day liberalism. Hiring a "good"
lawyer amounts to finding a professional who is best skilled at evading
the consequence of legal statutes. No wonder we want to cut their
amoral heads off. |
Holmes defined law as simply "the prophecies
of what the courts will do in fact." What, then, of the lawmaker?
If Supreme Court justices are in doubt about whether to create or
maintain a right of abortion, or legislators are in doubt about whether
to allow divorce on demand, they need to be told something more than
that whatever they enact will be law. They need to know how to
tell the difference between good law and bad law. Should the law
reflect traditional morality, or should it strike out in new directions
to further social utility and personal freedom? |
|
|
Holmes urged lawmakers to put aside
considerations of morality and tradition and to base law squarely on
rational policy, informed by scientific disciplines such as economics
and psychology. In short, to Holmes the practice of law was the
prediction of outcomes, the making of law was an exercise in policy
science, and the law itself was basically a statement about when the
state would use its overwhelming force to coerce its citizens. We
can see this concept of law in the modernist framing of the abortion
issue: morality becomes a matter of personal preference. The law
is concerned only with the extent to which state coercion should be
limited by considerations of personal freedom. |
|
To the twisted and amoral liberal mind, fundamental Christians or Jews
"informing" government on the subject of reality, represents a violation
of the doctrine of "separation of church and state." |
Similar to the observations of Sigmund Freud, Holmes
wasn't entirely wrong in his view. In his first letter to Timothy, the
Apostle Paul wrote in verses 8 to 10:
"...the law is not made for a righteous person, but
for the lawless and insubordinate, for the ungodly and for sinners, for the
unholy and profane, for murderers of fathers and murderers of mothers, for
manslayers, for fornicators, for homosexuals, for kidnappers, for liars, for
perjurers, and if there is any other thing that is contrary to sound
doctrine."
"...the law is good if one uses it lawfully."
While the Apostle Paul's teachings would certainly be
included with Holmes' "vaguer sanctions of conscience," this is no argument
against anchoring civil law in a theistic philosophic framework based on
transcendent absolutes. Contrary to liberal opinion, it is fully "lawful",
indeed imperative, for the Christian worldview to inform government (both
legislative and judicial) on how to maintain a civil society in a fallen world.
The alternatives are totalitarianism or anarchy, or both.
Vocationally, Christians are well suited to participate in
the political process. But therein lies the problem. The liberal
mind refuses to acknowledge either "transcendence" or "absolutes", and
consequently believe Christians are disqualified from serving. They engage
in discrimination!
According to current liberal ideology, the government and
its leaders must be entirely secular (naturalistic or atheistic) in viewpoint.
To support this argument and further their grip on power, they make the spurious
claim that government policies in-any-way linked to the theistic worldview
violate the so-called Constitutional principle of 'separation of church and
state'. Understandably, exceptions are made for religiously hypocritical
individuals who demonstrate that religious tenet in no way influences personal
behavior or legislative process.
Christians need to understand the absurdity of these
liberal arguments and counter them wherever found.
Mail this article to a friend
| |
- SEATED
- ASCENDED
- RAISED
- BURIED
- CRUCIFIED
General &
Special Revelation
Christian Agnosticism
|